As I mentioned in my previous
post, Fitzpatrick1 puts forward an interpretation of J.S. Mill which
compellingly shows how to resolve the apparent tensions in Mill’s works which
scholars have debated. I am intrigued by Fitzpatrick’s2 fourth
chapter, ‘The Rawlsian Objection’ because I wrote a contemporary political
philosophy essay on Rawls and liberalism a few years ago3. A
specific lecture for this module, out of which this essay arose, included an
examination of J.S. Mill’s political philosophy. However, for the purpose of
this essay, which involved an analysis of the set reading for the essay title,
I needed to focus on evaluating Rawls’s political liberalism and contemporary
responses to his theory of justice. This includes his criticism of previous
political liberalists who draw on what he generically refers to as classical
utilitarianism, under which he would include J.S. Mill. So I am interested in
looking at whether classical utilitarian liberalists can hold their own against
Rawls on the topic of freedom and justice but this time looking at it from the
other side of the debate. Fitzpatrick4 provides us with a picture of
this by showing how the classical utilitarian, especially J.S. Mill, could have
defended his views against Rawls’s criticisms.
Fitzpatrick’s analysis identifies
the pivotal claim in Rawls’s argument against classical utilitarian liberalists
as being that they rely on the principle of maximising utility for the greatest
number of people and that all their other principles are of secondary
importance because they merely arise from this principle5. Rawls
then builds on this claim by arguing that this leads to potentially
unacceptable results for individual freedoms and rights which makes classical
utilitarian liberalism a self-defeating, flawed approach6.
Fitzpatrick outlines various Rawlsian objections but highlights that he thinks the
strongest of the objections made by Rawls and his supporters is that classical
utilitarianism could:
“justify sacrificing one
person…..to avoid harms to others. Justice forbids sacrificing the freedom of
one person for another. Such a practice would not take the distinction between
persons seriously.”7
On reading this summary of Rawls’s
objection to classical utilitarian liberals, I asked myself whether this
sufficiently and accurately captured Rawls’s overall perspective on classical
utilitarianism over a cross-section of his works, especially how it related to
J.S. Mill. So I refreshed my memory of Rawls’s writings by looking through ‘A
Theory of Justice’, ‘Collected Papers’, and ‘Lectures on the History of Moral
Philosophy’.
When assessing Rawls’s ‘A Theory
of Justice’8, I was dissatisfied with his very broad-brush approach
to the wide range of classical utilitarianism. Rawls does acknowledge that
“There are many forms of utilitarianism” but nevertheless states that he will
“not survey these forms here, nor take account of the numerous refinements
found in contemporary discussions.”9 However, I think taking account
of at least some salient variations in classical utilitarianism would have
helped support Rawls’s theory of justice.
I think this because:
1) Rawls is partly building his
theory out of the so-called flaws he finds in classical utilitarianism and so
he is more likely to include erroneous flaws by lumping all variations into one
generic category and set of assumptions, irrespective of their differences in
approach. This leaves him open to criticisms, such as Fitzpatrick’s, which show
how Rawls’s criticisms do not sufficiently undermine a particular philosopher
or approach.
2) Rawls states his “aim” is to
provide “an alternative to all of these different versions of” utilitarianism10.
However, I think Rawls’s suggested alternative in his ‘A Theory of Justice’ is
weakened by his narrow, stereotypical depiction of classical utilitarianism. It
makes me wonder whether Rawls has fallen into the strawman fallacy problem of
characterising classical utilitarianism in a way which makes it easier for him
to knock down the approach in order to clear the way for his suggested
improvement on it.
3) Rawls states in his ‘A Theory
of Justice’ that when he says utilitarianism he will “describe…the strict
classical doctrine” the best example of which is Sidgwick11.
However, throughout this book, I noticed he does specify J.S. Mill in passages
on utilitarianism and sometimes argues against him. For instance, he specifies
passages in J.S. Mill and his principle of utility when he writes that,
although Mill can “support freedom”, Rawls argues his ‘justice as fairness’
approach is more convincing than J.S. Mill’s arguments concerning equal liberty12.
Furthermore, Rawls cites J.S.
Mill in his footnotes13 as a source when making general statements
depicting utilitarianism in general as holding that “the sum of advantages is
to be maximized” and that “justice” is “derivative …of…the greatest balance of
satisfaction.” Rawls also goes on to generalise that, for the utilitarian,
“there is no reason in principle why the greater gains of some should not
compensate for the lesser losses of others; …why the violation of the liberty
of a few might not be made right by the greater good shared by many”…… “it is
right for a society to maximize the net balance of satisfaction taken over all
its members.”14 These passages, I think, support Fitzpatrick as
accurately describing Rawls’s description of classical utilitarianism and how
he includes J.S. Mill within it. Fitzpatrick15 is certainly right in
claiming that Rawls is interpreting J.S. Mill as a maximising utilitarian who
makes his principle of utility central to his arguments, because many passages
point to Rawls emphasising J.S. Mill’s maximising approach and talking about
the principle of utility as primary and justice as secondary.
However, Fitzpatrick’s16
central claim for his interpretation of J.S. Mill is that he was not a
maximising utilitarian and that the problem lies with reading Mill in this way.
Hence, Fitzpatrick argues scholars who read Mill as a maximising utilitarian
are misguided in their claims that Mill is inconsistent or incoherent. So Fitzpatrick’s
book aims to show that these internal tensions disappear on his
re-interpretation of J.S. Mill. Indeed, J.S. Mill’s commitment to “liberalism,
liberal feminism, representative democracy, individual rights”17, amongst
other things, means it should be quite obvious to us that he would not be
attracted to a maximising approach in the first place.
1Fitzpatrick, J.R.
(2006), “John Stuart Mill’s Political Philosophy”, Continuum Studies in British
Philosophy, Continuum
2ibid
3 available at:
4 Fitzpatrick, J.R.
(2006), “John Stuart Mill’s Political Philosophy”, Continuum Studies in British
Philosophy, Continuum
5 ibid p129
6 ibid chapter 4
7 ibid p146
8 Rawls, J. (1971) “A Theory of Justice”, The Belknap Press
of Harvard University Press
9 ibid p22
10 ibid
11 ibid
12 ibid p209-210
13 ibid p26
14 ibid
15 Fitzpatrick, J.R.
(2006), “John Stuart Mill’s Political Philosophy”, Continuum Studies in British
Philosophy, Continuum
16 ibid
17ibid p129
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.